Imágenes de páginas
PDF
EPUB

more for the novelty o otherwise, did not go I had concluded with opinion could be no othe madness; and questioning su who had been there, I perceived made a jest thereof, except one, w told me that the business was not altogether to be laughed at: and because the man was reputed by me to be very intelligent and wary, I'repented that I was not there, and began from that time forward, as oft as I met with any one of the Copernican persuasion, to demand of them if they had been always of the same judgment. Of as many as I examined I found not so much as one who told me not that he had been a long time of the contrary opinion, but to have changed it for this, as convinced by the strength of the reasons proving the same; and afterwards questioning them one by one, to see whether they were well possessed of the reasons of the other side, I found them all to be very ready and perfect in them, so that I could not truly say that they took this opinion out of ignorance, vanity, or to show the acuteness of their wits. On the contrary, of as many of the Peripatetics and Ptolemeans as I have asked, (and out of curiosity I have talked with many,) what pains they had taken in the book of Copernicus, I found very few that had so much as superficially perused it, but of those who I thought had understood the same, not one: and, moreover, I have inquired amongst the followers of the Peripatetic doctrine, if ever any of them had held the contrary opinion, and likewise found none that had. Whereupon, considering that there was no man who followed the opinion of Copernicus that had not been first on the contrary side, and that was not very well acquainted with the reasons of Aristotle and Ptolemy, and, on the contrary, that there was not one of the followers of Ptolemy that had ever been of the judgment of Copernicus, and had left that to embrace this of Aristotle ;-considering, I say, these things, I began to think that one who leaveth an opinion imbued with his milk and followed by very many, to take up another, owned by very few, and denied by all the schools, and that really seems a great paradox, must needs have been moved, not to say forced, by more powerful reasons. For this cause I am become very curious to dive, as they say, into the bottom of this business." It seems improbable that Galileo should think

The
termissi
though in its
with Galileo's o
tion. Urstisius
as possibly Salus
when alluding t
mathematical p
1567, and sever
still extant. In
that he publishe
Purbach's Thec
died at Bâle in i
about twenty-tw

It is not unlik
part, owed his er
lar prejudices to
dano Bruno, an
unsparing boldn
and absurdities
cial murder, ar
heretic and infid
cutioners endeav
for the purpose
own atrocious cr.
at Rome in 1600
supposes, on ac
della Bestia tri
this book has le
was directed a
Rome, to which
est degree relat
fashionable phil
reason and ridic
sages in his writi
as they generally
completely outst
he lived. Amor
nions, he believe.
sisted of innum
with assemblag
round each of th
the smallness of
their being obs
marked further,
improbable tha
planets revolvin
which we have n
account of their
mote distance fi
asserting that a
stars are really
not sufficiently p
enormous distan

difficult to estin

[ocr errors][merged small]
[ocr errors]

long observation that we can determine if any of these move round each other, or what other motions they may have." He ridiculed the Aristotelians in no very measured terms-" They harden themselves, and heat themselves, and embroil themselves for Aristotle; they call themselves his champions, they Fate all but Aristotle's friends, they are ready to live and die for Aristotle, and yet they do not understand so much as the titles of Aristotle's chapters." And in another place he introduces an Aristotelian inquiring, "Do you take Plato for an ignoramus-Aristotle for an ass?" to whom he answers, My son, I neither call them asses, nor you mules,—them baboons, nor you apes, as you would have me: I told you that I esteem them the heroes of the world, but I will not credit them without sufficient reason; and if you were not both blind and deaf, you would understand that I must disbelieve their absurd and contradictory assertions." Bruno's works, though in general considered those of a visionary and madman, were in very extensive circulation, probably not the less eagerly sought after from being included among the books prohibited by the Romish church; and although it has been reserved for later observations to furnish complete verification of his most daring speculations, yet there was enough, abstractedly taken, in the wild freedom of his remarks, to attract a mind like Galileo's; and it is with more satisfaction that we refer the formation of his opinions to a man of undoubted though eccentric genius, like Bruno, than to such as Maestlin, who, though a diligent and careful observer, seems seldom to have taken any very enlarged views of the science on which he was engaged.

With a few exceptions similar to those above mentioned, the rest of Galileo's contemporaries well deserved the contemptuous epithet which he fixed on them of Paper Philosophers, for, to use his own words, in a letter to Kepler on this subject, "this sort of men fancied philosophy was to be studied like the Eneid or Odyssey, and that the true reading of nature was to be detected by the collation of texts." Galileo's own method of philosophizing was widely different; seldom omitting to bring with every new assertion the test of experiment, either directly in confirmation of it, or tending to show its probability and consistency. We have already seen that

De l'Infinito Universo. Dial. 3. La Cena de le Cenere, 1584.

he engaged in a series of experiments to investigate the truth of some of Aristotle's positions. As fast as he succeeded in demonstrating the falsehood of any of them, he denounced them from his professorial chair with an energy and success which irritated more and more against him the other members of the academic body.

There seems something in the stubborn opposition which he encountered in establishing the truth of his mechanical theorems, still more stupidly absurd than in the ill will to which, at a later period of his life, his astronomical opinions exposed him: it is intelligible that the vulgar should withhold. their assent from one who pretended to discoveries in the remote heavens, which few possessed instruments to verify, or talents to appreciate; but it is difficult to find terms for stigmatizing the obdurate folly of those who preferred the evidence of their books to that of their senses, in judging of phenomena so obvious as those, for instance, presented by the fall of bodies to the ground. Aristotle had asserted, that if two different weights of the same material were let fall from the same height, the heavier one would reach the ground sooner than the other, in the proportion of their weights. The experiment is certainly not a very difficult one, but nobody thought of that method of argument, and consequently this assertion had been long received, upon his word, among the axioms of the science of motion. Galileo ventured to appeal from the authority of Aristotle to that of his own senses, and maintained that, with the exception of an inconsiderable difference, which he attributed to the disproportionate resistance of the air, they would fall in the same time. The Aristotelians ridiculed and refused to listen to such an idea. Galileo repeated his experiments in their presence from the famous leaning tower at Pisa: and with the sound of the simultaneously falling weights still ringing in their ears, they could persist in gravely maintaining that a weight of ten pounds would reach the ground in a tenth part of the time taken by one of a single pound, because they were able to quote chapter and verse in which Aristotle assures them that such is the fact. A temper of mind like this could not fail to produce ill will towards him who felt no scruples in exposing their wilful folly; and the watchful malice of these men soon found the means of making Galileo desirous of quitting

work
culati

em

and fi
hands
to publ.
denounce Galileo
ship as the pret
plagiarist. He w
beloved and est
that they vied wit
ing affronts of this
and in more tha
relieved, by their
answers, from the
his own character
To this epoch
be referred his re-
mometer. The
useful instrument
mathematician He

his situation at Pisa. Don Giovan
de' Medici, a natural son of Cosme
who possessed a slight knowledge o
mechanics on which he prided himself,
had proposed a contrivance for cleans-
ing the port of Leghorn, on the effi-
ciency of which Galileo was consulted.
His opinion was unfavourable, and the v
violence of the inventor's disappoint-
ment, (for Galileo's judgment was veri- eac
fied by the result,) took the somewhat was
unreasonable direction of hatred to- of
wards the man whose penetration had
foreseen the failure. Galileo's situation
was rendered so unpleasant by the ma-
chinations of this person, that he de-
cided on accepting overtures elsewhere,
which had already been made to him;
accordingly, under the negotiation of his
staunch friend Guido Ubaldi, and with
the consent of Ferdinand, he procured
from the republic of Venice a nomina-
tion for six years to the professorship of
mathematics in the university of Padua,
whither he removed in September 1592.
Galileo's predecessor in the mathe-
matical chair at Padua was Moleti, who
died in 1588, and the situation had re-
mained unfilled during the intervening
four years. This seems to show that
the directors attributed but little im-
portance to the knowledge which it was
the professor's duty to impart. This in-
ference is strengthened by the fact, that
the amount of the annual salary at-
tached to it did not exceed 180 florins,
whilst the professors of philosophy and
civil law, in the same university, were
rated at the annual stipends of 1400
and 1680 florins.* Galileo joined the
university about a year after its triumph
over the Jesuits, who had established a
school in Padua about the year 1542,
and, increasing yearly in influence, had
shown symptoms of a design to get the
whole management of the public edu-
cation into the hands of their own
body. After several violent disputes it
was at length decreed by the Venetian
senate, in 1591, that no Jesuit should
be allowed to give instruction at Padua
in any of the sciences professed in the
university. It does not appear that after
this decree they were again troublesome
to the university, but this first decree
against them was followed, in 1606,
by a second more peremptory, which
banished them entirely from the Vene-
tian territory. Galileo would of course
find his fellow-professors much embit-

[blocks in formation]

self, who has been
ventor by Italian
time claimed it
him. In 1638, (
sarini that " he re

ment shown to h

five years back by
small glass bottle,
hen's egg, the neck
two inches long,
straw. Having w
his hands, and t
mouth into a ves
little water, and w
of his hand from
rose in the neck of
eleven inches abov
sel, and Galileo em
in the construction
measuring heat an
a Venetian noblem..
who has been al
Galileo's friend ar
him in the followin
brought the instru
vented for measuri
convenient and per
the difference of t
two rooms is seen

[ocr errors]
[ocr errors][ocr errors][merged small][merged small][merged small]

grees." This date is anterior to the claims both of Santorio and Drebbel, & Dutch physician, who was the first to introduce it into Holland.

Galileo's thermometer, as we have just seen, consisted merely of a glass tube ending in a bulb, the air in which, being partly expelled by heat, was replaced by water from a glass into which the open end of the tube was plunged, and the different degrees of temperature were indicated by the expansion of the air which yet remained in the bulb, so that the scale would be the reverse of that of the thermometer now in use, for the water would stand at the highest level in the coldest weather. It was, in truth, a barometer also, in consequence of the communication between the tube and external air, although Galileo did not intend it for this purpose, and when he attempted to determine the relative weight of the air, employed a contrivance still more imperfect than this rude barometer would have been. A passage among his posthumous fragments intimates that he subsequently used spirit of wine instead of water.

Viviani attributes an improvement of this imperfect instrument, but without specifying its nature, to Ferdinand II., a pupil and subsequent patron of Galile, and, after the death of his father Cosmo, reigning duke of Florence. It was still further improved by Ferdirand's younger brother, Leopold de' Medici, who invented the modern process of expelling all the air from the tube by boiling the spirit of wine in it, and of hermetically sealing the end of the tube, whilst the contained liquid is in this expanded state, which deprived it of its barometrical character, and first made it an accurate thermometer. The final improvement was the employment of mercury instead of spirit of wine, which is recommended by Lana so early as 1670, on account of its equable expansion. For further details on the history and use of this instrument, the reader may consult the Treatises on the THERMOMETER and PYROMEter.

[merged small][merged small][ocr errors][merged small]

ding the first notice which we find of his having embraced the doctrines of the Copernican astronomy. Most of our readers are aware of the principles of the theory of the celestial motions which Copernicus restored; but the number of those who possess much knowledge of the cumbrous and unwieldy system which it superseded is perhaps more limited. The present is not a fit opportunity to enter into many details respecting it; these will find their proper place in the History of Astronomy: but a brief sketch of its leading principles is necessary to render what follows intelligible.

The earth was supposed to be immoveably fixed in the centre of the universe, and immediately surrounding it the atmospheres of air and fire, beyond which the sun, moon, and planets, were thought to be carried round the earth, fixed each to a separate orb or heaven of solid but transparent matter. The order of distance in which they were supposed to be placed with regard to the central earth was as follows: The Moon, Mercury, Venus, The Sun, Mars, Jupiter, and Saturn. It became a question in the ages immediately preceding Copernicus, whether the Sun was not nearer the Earth than Mercury, or at least than Venus; and this question was one on which the astronomical theorists were then chiefly divided.

We possess at this time a curious record of a former belief in this arrangement of the Sun and planets, in the order in which the days of the week have been named from them. According to the dreams of Astrology, each planet was supposed to exert its influence in succession, reckoning from the most distant down to the nearest, over each hour of the twenty-four. The planet which was supposed to predominate over the first hour, gave its name to that day. The general reader will trace this curious fact more easily with the French or Latin names than with the English, which have been translated into the titles of the corresponding Saxon deities. Placing the Sun and planets in the following order, and beginning, for instance, with Monday, or the Moon's day; Saturn ruled the second hour of that day, Jupiter the third, and so round till we come again and again to the Moon on the 8th, 15th, and 22d hours; Saturn ruled the 23d,

*Dion Cassius, lib. 37.

[blocks in formation]

The other stars were supposed to be fixed in an outer orb, beyond which were two crystalline spheres, (as they were called,) and on the outside of all, the primum mobile or first moveable, which sphere was supposed to revolve round the earth in twenty-four hours, and by its friction, or rather, as most of the philosophers of that day chose to term it, by the sort of heavenly influence which it exercised on the interior orbs, to carry them round with a similar motion. Hence the diversity of day and night. But beside this principal and general motion, each orb was supposed to have one of its own, which was intended to account for the apparent changes of position of the planets with respect to the fixed stars and to each other. This supposition, however, proving insufficient to account for all the irregularities of motion observed, two hypotheses were introduced.-First, that to each planet belonged several concentric spheres or heavens, casing each other like the coats of an onion, and, secondly, that the centres of these solid spheres, with which the planet revolved, were placed in the circumference of a secondary revolving sphere, the centre of which secondary sphere was situated at the earth. They thus acquired the names of Eccentrics or Epicycles, the latter word signifying a circle upon a circle. The whole art of astronomers

as then directed towards inventing and

SU

ca
tot.

asse
say

[ocr errors]
[ocr errors][ocr errors][ocr errors]

midd. point of
who are called Pyr
in Italy, are of
For they say that re
and that the earth,
them, is one of the s
change of day and h
tion, with which it
centre." It might
this passage alone, w
gorean theory embr
diurnal motion of can't bat a
tle farther, we find the
Some, as we have
to be one of the st
it is placed in the c
and revolves on a ‹

[ocr errors]

The pretended tran
Arabic version of Aristar

di," in which the Coperu
loped, is spurious. Mena
tions on Diogen. Laert. 1
(Ed. Amst. 1692.) The
authorities well worth
toire de l'Astronomie, inf
some opinions which Arc
Aristarchus. A more d

from the following blunde
Astronomers had been

in different parts of her
from the sun. Roberval
tarchus the credit of hav
duced into his book, not
but an explanation of
makes Aristarchus give a
gee (or place of greatest d
always be at the north st

was there, or nearly so,
knew not but that it had
however moveable, and
was nearly half way bet
noxes. He therefore w
reason for the necessity
he observed anything on
observed the contrary.
of the earth's axis to th
time of Roberval, and he
the proper value which it
+ De Colo. lib, 2,

འ་ ༦

reci

« AnteriorContinuar »